A pragmatic clarification of Truth
A common view of certain philosophical circles that lean towards relativism holds
that theories of truth cannot engage with a naïve form of realism, like the one defended,
they claim, by the doctrines of truth, understood either as correspondence or coherence.
There is a huge amount of literature on the topic and the debates usually confront
very serious objections. Many interpreters considered pragmatic doctrines of truth
as spurious and quickly dismissed them as inconsistent. Those readers suppose that
pragmatists write either from the correspondentist point of view or from a coherentist
stance, when they state on truth.
I believe neither of the classical pragmatists adopted the alleged dichotomy that
opposes coherentist and correspondentist accounts: indeed, neither Peirce nor James
intended to offer an account of the «definition» of truth; they were rather concerned
with a «pragmatic clarification of truth» and the things at stake in that clarification
are not definitional aspects of truth, but the consequences of our understanding of
truth within the context of the rational interpretation of inquiry in action. According
to this, the definitional approach with regards to truth must be understood through
the norms of rational and self-controlled inquiry, and this circumstance must impinge
in the definitional aspects, and not the other way around.
However, common sense considerations about truth ought not to be considered far away
from the pragmatic ones. Consider, thus, when inquiry is carried out: we would never
knowingly rest in a conclusion we believe as false. Inquiry takes some common sense
considerations for granted, but there are many aspects of common sense that might
not always be accepted as rational. Inquiry is, thus, a higher concept that engages
with a goal-directed activity carried rationally.
There is a sense, though, in which we might have to deny that truth is the aim of
inquiry: for example, if we adopt a minimalist theory of truth, the concept of truth
is just a platitude for what we already believe: saying that I believe that ‘p’ is
true is nothing more than saying that I believe ‘p’ and then saying that the aim of
my inquiry is to believe something that I already believe; therefore, it cannot be
an end.
A strand of neo-pragmatists that include Richard Rorty think that is better to endorse
a weaker goal. Perhaps it will be about enough if we follow certain norms for thinking
rationally and, then, only adopt some conditions for warranted assertions. Those views,
however, come across as, conceptually, very thin, because they do not actually tell
us when an inquiry is satisfied and when it ought to stop -for example, it is the
case of sciences, where we know that some answer is accepted as satisfactory because
our practical goal is a pattern of satisfactory explanations for a given problem that
count as an acceptable solution.
Peirce’s pragmatism somehow accepted that truth cannot be the end of inquiry. He provided us of a theory of the settlement of belief which he christened
as «the method of science». In Peirce’s theory, truth is equivalent to a state of
settlement of a belief, but he never implies that such settlement has to be a permanent
state. However, Pierce’s method is itself a pragmatic clarification of truth for it
thinks of truth as the gravitational center around which rationally settled beliefs
gravitate and that towards which they tend to. This will be a key concept henceforth:
rather than a consensus on what is believed to be the truth, then, stands the «convergence»
towards truth, accordingly, i.e., the settlement of a goal-directed inquiry.
Cheryl Misak explains us that the pragmatic Peircean conception of truth must involve
an account of how can beliefs turn out «indefeasible» or «superassertible» (to use
the equivalent concept popularized by Crispin Wright). The concept of an indefeasible
belief is a relevant one, but cannot be properly understood outside what Peirce recognized
as the realism that pragmatism presupposes. We will come to reach this problem further
below. But first let us delve on those considerations mentioned above in the details
of the account provided by Cheryl Misak.
Misak on Truth as the Aim of Inquiry
In Truth and the End of Inquiry (Misak, 2004), Cheryl Misak provides a Peircean account of truth. She endeavors in the rather
onerous task of locating a pragmatist account of truth in Peirce’s body of doctrines.
She means to accomplish an account of objectivity capable of overcoming Davidson’s
objections and criticisms to objectivity as the grounds for truth, amongst other concerns.
This sort of objectivity will involve subjunctive conditionals of the form: «If you
were to do x, then y would result». She concurs with Peirce at thinking that it is correct to say that
a true hypothesis is one that would be believed at the end of inquiry.
However, the core of Misak’s Peircean account -which is given in the two famous papers
from the series Illustrations on the Logic of Science: “How to Make our Ideas Clear” (1878) and “The Fixation of Belief” (1877)- is that
the views included in those papers were held unaltered by Peirce over the years, ever
since he formulated them, in spite of Peirce’s own further and significant philosophical
development. I am going to assume the same claim, but with a pinch of salt.
I propose that, even though Peirce never changed his views as contained in those materials, he nonetheless changed the focus by which they should be understood. Substantively, indeed. I take, for example, his «Scholastic Realism» as the view that represents
his mature thought. This view distanced Peirce from his early views in important issues,
actually.
I will offer more argumentative ammunition on this at the last section of this paper.
However, for now, it matters to highlight what I consider to be a very remarkable
insight in Misak’s interpretation of Peirce: i.e., the way she understands the conditional
sentence that expresses the pragmatic clarification of Truth in her Peircean account.
Consider a definitional or constitutive theory of Truth. It will offer, primarily, a biconditional of the following sort:
Given that H is the result of an inquiry, H is true if and only if inquiry was pursued as far as it could fruitfully go; then, H would be believed to be true.
This formulation seems to reflect the Peircean account, but weakly so, since assumes
that H is a stable state of belief. The risk of such formulation is an identification such
as H↔T, where H is a finite premise and T a consequence that can be formulated in a particular proposition and that fully reflects
truth.
Misak interprets that the latter would certainly be enough for a basic definition
of truth, though a family of objections might be raised to other uses of the term
«Truth». For example, how can the latter sentence account for coherence or the problem that there are facts for which we have no possible access to (for
example, how many times Winston Churchill sneezed in 1949)? Thusly, she thinks that
Peirce provides us of a relevant case of conceiving the consequences of the truth
of a hypothesis:
It is a consequence of «H is true» that, if inquiry were to be pursued, H would be believed.
This conditional does not move from inquiry to truth, as the definitional (constitutive)
version does, but from truth to the deliverances of inquiry. This inversion aims to
match with our uses of the concept in a better way: it does not force us to say that
truth is an individual proposition. This has a liberating effect: we would want to
call true a family of propositions that direct us to the settlement of belief, instead
of a fixed and permanent proposition. In addition, Peirce thinks that there is no
more to truth that what inquiry would offer us to settle upon. Then, saying that H is true cannot mean anything transcendental or permanently veiled to continuous and
selfcontrolled inquiry. Inquiry will give us beliefs that we would want to call true.
Questions on objectivity, bivalence and Truth
Many objections directed against theories of truth come from a property of truth called
«bivalence»: a proposition/belief cannot be both false and true. But, what if it happens
to be neither of those? What if it is permanently indeterminate, because its truth
cannot be corroborated or settled?
Let me bring the case of the so-called «buried facts» forward again: there is no way
to know, according to Misak, how many Tyrannosaurus Rex there were about in the Jurassic
period.1 Thus, shall we rather give up theories of truth altogether, due to those buried and
unachievable facts for which the evidence is not available for us anymore (no matter
how good enough and well enough we inquire into it)? I think we certainly should accept
the fact that absolute bivalence cannot be the case. This matter, however, does not
affect, as far as I can see, the important and, as Misak calls it, «uncontentious»
claim about Truth and the inquirer: the philosopher and the inquirer ought to adopt
the «method of science» not because there is a determinate answer to every possible
question, but because the structure of reality seems to offer us convergence: a convergence
into fewer answers to multiple questions that are raised by the irritation that genuine
doubts impinge upon us.
Thus, for instance, it will be rather idle to try to find out evidence for the question
that the world was created five minutes ago (as Bertrand Russell creatively put it),
because there is hardly anything that counts as evidence for that. Genuine doubts
are settled by beliefs that turn out to be indefeasible, i.e., that gravitate and
point to relevant and continuous evidence. Peirce thought that artificial and unauthentic
doubts crop up from nominalist scruples. Nominalists only accept some items as real,
dumping others apart and, thereby, they open the door to all sorts of skepticisms.
The pragmatic conception of truth, that the inquirer ought to adopt, according to
Peirce, is restrained to: “Truth as can and ought to be used as a guide for conduct”
(1913, MS 684: 11).
Misak, agreeing with the above, reckons that this is a case of the conditional description
of truth that goes from inquiry to truth. She remarks the same issue:
Truth is the property of those beliefs that would encounter no recalcitrant experience,
broadly construed. Truth is the property of those beliefs that a sufficiently pursued
experience-constrained inquiry would turn up. And (T-I): we must assume that if a
hypothesis is true, then if we were to inquire about it, eventually something would
impinge upon us to convince us of its truth (Misak 2004: 160).
Misak holds that there are many virtues for an account of truth so construed: Her
account of Peircean truth: 1) provides a rational context for inquiry to proceed, 2) makes sense of the practice of inquiry as the search for truth, and 3) provides and justifies methodology. Hence, all things being equal, whatever the method
of inference (induction, deduction and abduction) we pick our inferences on, we can
nonetheless rely that the method of science applied will lead us to converge with
the structure of experience broadly constructed.
Fallibilism, Inquiry and Realism
Richard Rorty thought that there are some pragmatic arguments that can prevent us
of believing that truth is the aim of inquiry: he offers a slogan that states:
This means that if I want to carry out any kind of investigation, let us say, for
catching a train going from York to Edinborough, I need to be able to identify the
aims of what I have to do in order to not miss the transportation. However, that is
somehow far from a definitive truth, because sometimes the means to obtain my goal
might differ: I could use the board at the railway station, I could browse time departures
online, I could ask a friend and so forth. It will be misled to say that a particular
mean is truer than another. Means are just good relatively to what I need.
Furthermore, it might happen that whatever we consider true as of now, eventually
turns out to be false, as it has effectively happened numerous times in the history
of knowledge, or rather in the history of fallible long-held beliefs. A classical
example of this could be the shift from modern Newtonian physics to the contemporary
complex not-unified physics that is partly governed by General Relativity for the
macro-universe and Quantum Mechanics for the micro-universe. In such situation (as
of today) there is no shared truth between these two governing theories. Rorty’s challenge
can be summarized as follows: if fallibilism is the case, truth cannot be the aim
of inquiry.
Rorty’s challenge might be better understood by revisiting Davidson’s thoughts on
the consequences of fallibilism. Davidson (2005) argues that if fallibilism is the case, truth cannot be the end of inquiry, as the
end of inquiry is objective and objectivity is problematic (to say the least) because:
a) truths do not come with a mark like the date in the corner of a photograph that distinguishes
them from falsehoods, b) It also states that however long and well we inquire, we shall be left with fallible
beliefs, and c) We will never know for certain which of our beliefs are true.
Peirce was not far from understanding the challenge posted by Rorty. As Chris Hookway
tells us, Peirce actually provided a theory of fallibilism long before the better-known
theories of Popper about fallibility in science (2007: 21). Peirce was sure that we
cannot be absolutely certain of the truth of a belief; no matter how settled the belief appears to be.
Still, he does not reject truth altogether. Misak seems to affirm that Peirce’s move
stands the challenge of understanding truth as an aim of inquiry because there are
some beliefs that turn out to be indefeasible, and we are better off if we adopt them,
unless we have real grounds to doubt them. Why is this conduct better than rejecting
truth altogether? The answer is quite clear: preserving a minimal account of truth
provides us of an account of the norms that should govern inquiry. These norms offer
us an explanation of the means to find pragmatic consequences. Explanations of this
kind will naturally be a matter, of course, if inquiry were fruitfully taken.
This strategy proves much better than the relativistic one with regards to their approach
to truth: it provides us with a regulative hope about inquiry and its aims. We call
beliefs «true» when we are epistemically warranted about their settlement, albeit
they can only be approximately true.
Fallibilism, therefore, rather than a fatal strike to the concept of truth, is a way
of being epistemically aware of error-sensitiveness and refinement of our best theories.
I find very enlightening the mentioned pragmatistic move, though I do not think it
is enough to achieve a minimal account of truth. As Peirce acknowledged, if we want
to aim for the best explanation of why there are regulative patterns in all sorts
of inquiries, then we still need to accept a first and foremost important hypothesis
that explains why there are pervasive patterns in the first place: he called this
the «hypothesis of reality».
Indeed, Peirce provided an account of truth by offering an account of reality. If
reality impinges upon our inquiries in a pervasive and regulated way it will be plausible
to accept that certain items considered by our inquiries have to be held as real.
Realism, thence, is in the summit of the theory: one cannot be wholly pragmatist without
finding reasonable the expectations of the subjective conditionals of inquiry and
only the hypothesis of reality makes them wholly reasonable and a matter of course.
Pragmatists like Andrew Reynolds and myself propose that the statistical approximation
to the ideal limit that the pragmatist conception of truth conveys is due to a realism
that Peirce called Synechism. Synechism is the hypothesis that there is real continuity
operative in nature. The continuity of habits gives a metaphysical explanation of
regularity. This account cannot be fully introduced here, but it gives a good clue
as to how Peirce wanted the matter to be reconsidered.
Consider, finally, the case of the inquiry that eventually became the theory of gases
developed by Clausius, Maxwell and Boltzmann (Garber, 1970). Such a theory is only possible as long as it is able to avoid accounting for each
of the particles in a confined given gas, in order to focus the attention in the behavior
of the gas as a continuum with different patterns. The behavior of these patterns
provides statistical information and different proportional relations of idealized
variables. In the same wise, the realism proposed by Peircean pragmatism is a realism
of habits understood as pervasive regularities that become the content of what we
can, afterwards, call, laws of nature, comfortably.
Now, the way in which Peirce dealt with this problem is present in: his category «realism»,
his objective idealism and his theory of signs. Each of these doctrines build up towards
a substantive theory of reality that ultimately will provide us of a pragmatic account
of truth. Here, I will stop, but not without mentioning these elements of his architectonic
system or without stressing the importance of them to account for truth as the aim
of inquiry. Misak’s account might not fully tackle all the issues related to truth.
We need more substantive elements to correlate reality and inquiry. Nonetheless, she
provided us of a fresh start, free of scruples in relation to truth. After all, for
a pragmatist and for pragmatic purposes, to be «methodologically realist» means nothing
else but being a «realist». Peirce would even add that it means to be an «Extreme
Scholastic Realist».